CS Wiki | Cedric Schwyter

Mathematical Reasoning, Proofs, and a First Approach to Logic

Mathematical Reasoning, Proofs, and a First Approach to Logic

Mathematical Statements

πŸ’‘ A mathematical statement that is either true or false is also called a proposition.

πŸ’‘ A true proposition is often called a theorem, a lemma, or a corollary. A proposition not known to be true or false is often called a conjecture or an assumption.

The Concept of a Proof

πŸ’‘ (Informal.) A proof of a statement is a sequence of simple, easily verifiable, consecutive steps. The proof starts from a set of axioms (things postulated to be true) and known (previously proved) facts. Each step corresponds to the application of a derivation rule to a few already proven statements, resulting in a newly proved statement, until the final step results in .

A First Introduction to Propositional Logic

πŸ’‘ The logical values (constants) β€œtrue” and β€œfalse” are usually denoted as 1 and 0, respectively.

πŸ’‘ Logical operators:

  1. The negation (logical NOT) of a proposition , denoted as , is true if and only if is false.
  2. The conjunction (logical AND) of two propositions and , denoted , is true if and only if both and are true.
  3. The disjunction (logical OR) of two propositions and , denoted , is true if and only if or (or both) are true.

πŸ’‘ (Informal.) The implication of two propositions and , denoted as , is equivalent to .

πŸ’‘ (Informal.) The two-sided implication of two propositions and , denoted as , is equivalent to .

πŸ’‘ A correctly formed expression involving the propositional symbols , , ,… and logical operators is called a formula (of propositional logic).

πŸ’‘ Two formulas and (in propositional logic) are called equivalent, denoted as , if they correspond to the same function, i.e., if the truth values are equal for all truth assignments to the propositional symbols appearing in or .

πŸ“Œ 1) and (idempotence)

2) and (commutativity of and )

3) and (associativity)

4) and (absorption)

5) (first distributive law)

6) (second distributive law)

7) (double negation)

8) and (de Morgan’s rules).

πŸ’‘ A formula is a logical consequence of a formula , denoted

if for all truth assignments to the propositional symbols appearing in or , the truth value of is 1 if the truth value of is 1.

πŸ’‘ Two formulas and are equivalent if and only if each one is a logical consequence of the other, i.e.,

πŸ’‘ A formula (in propositional logic) is called a tautology or valid if it is true for all truth assignments of the involved propositional symbols. One often writes to say that is a tautology.

πŸ’‘ A formula (in propositional logic) is called satisfiable if it is true for at least one truth assignment of the involved propositional symbols, and it is called unsatisfiable otherwise.

πŸ’‘ The symbol is sometimes used to denote a tautology, and the symbol is sometimes used to denote an unsatisfiable formula. One sometimes writes to say that is a tautology, and to say that is unsatisfiable. For any formula we have

πŸ“Œ A formula is a tautology if and only if is unsatisfiable.

πŸ“Œ For any formulas and , is a tautology if and only if .

A First Introduction to Predicate Logic

πŸ’‘ A -ary predicate on is a function

πŸ’‘ For a universe and a predicate we define the following logical statements:

  • stands for: is true for all in .
  • stands for: is true for some in , i.e., there exists an for which is true.

More generally, for a formula with a variable , which for each value is either true or false, the formula is true if and only if is true for all in , and the formula is true if and only if is true for some in .

πŸ’‘ Some useful rules:

Logical Formulas vs. Mathematical Statements

πŸ“Œ For any two formulas and , if , then

is true.

Some Proof Patterns

πŸ’‘ The proof step of composing implications is as follows: If and are both true, then one concludes that is also true.

πŸ“Œ (transitivity of )*

πŸ’‘ A direct proof of an implication works by assuming and then proving under this assumption.

πŸ’‘ An indirect proof of an implication proceeds by assuming that is false and proving that is false, under this assumption.

πŸ“Œ

πŸ’‘ A proof of a statement by use of the so-called modus ponens proceeds in three steps:

  1. Find a suitable mathematical statement .
  2. Prove .
  3. Prove .

πŸ“Œ .

πŸ’‘ A proof of a statement by case distinction proceeds in three steps:

  1. Find a finite list of mathematical statements (the cases).
  2. Prove that one of the is true (one case occurs).
  3. Prove for .

πŸ“Œ For every we have

πŸ’‘ A proof by contradiction of a statement proceeds in three steps:

  1. Find a suitable mathematical statement .
  2. Prove that is false.
  3. Assume that is false and prove (from this assumption) that is true (a contradiction).

πŸ“Œ .

πŸ’‘ Consider a set of parameters and for each a statement, denoted . An existence proof is a proof of the statement that is true for at least one . An existence proof is constructive if it exhibits an for which is true, and otherwise it is non-constructive.

πŸ“– The Pigeonhole Principle: If a set of objects is partitioned into sets, then at least one of these sets contains at least objects.

πŸ’‘ Consider a set of parameters and for each a statement, denoted . A proof by counterexample is a proof of the statement that is not true for all , by exhibiting an (called counterexample) such that is false. This corresponds to an existence proof.

πŸ’‘ Proof by induction:

  1. Basis step. Prove .
  2. Induction step. Prove that for any arbitrary we have .

πŸ“– For the universe and an arbitrary unary predicate we have

This project is maintained by D3PSI